1. INTRODUCTION
Three centuries ago the Enlightenment proclaimed boldly that it
had discovered the source of man's unhappiness in society and
offered the world a set of concepts with which to successfully
pursue happiness.
During the years since that bold proclamation material production
has boomed within the economic and political power structures
of western civilization that were built from the Enlightenment's
social engineering blueprints. But these structures and the boom
they set off have not quelled the war of all against all. The
last century was the bloodiest in history. The Enlightenment accomplished
the attenuation of the church's political power in western civilization,
as it set out to do. But liberated from the burden of the virtues
pressed on him by the church secularized Economic Man is still
unhappy in his life. Our social cohesiveness continues to be eaten
away by something.
The current state of affairs may be a signal that there are tensions
in human association that cannot be held adequately in balance.
But I am not convinced that it is. I think the current state of
affairs is a signal that the Enlightenment failed, and we have
up 'til now failed, to correctly identify the corrosive force
within human society and to understand how it destroys. I think
once properly identified the corrosive force can be got rid of.
Moreover, I suggest that far from ridding us of the corrosive
force at work in human society the Enlightenment exposed every
nook and cranny of life to it. And I suggest that we have failed
during the last bloodsoaked century to stem that corrosive infiltration
because we have allowed our minds to be ensnared in the bitter
black tangle of the Enlightenment's radical errors and oversights
and misbegotten concepts.
The purpose of this essay is to clear a path out of the dark tangle
bequeathed to us by the Enlightenment, and then to properly identify
the source of societal dissolution. In order to clear that path
I will correct the following errors:
-- The radical Enlightenment error that man is by nature solitary
and at bottom motivated by a fear of death.
-- The Enlightenment's disregard of Aristotle's concept of Right
Desire and of the power of the desire for Valued Place.
-- The Enlightenment's blank failure to analyze the Privilege
To Waste that lies concealed within the conventions of property
ownership.
--The Enlightenment notions of liberty and right,
misbegotten from the above errors.
2. MISBEGOTTEN NOTIONS
I begin the path-clearing with a look at two
well-known notions that have come from the lexicon of the Enlightenment
and which have been used almost universally by contemporary social
and political philosophers to ill-effect -- liberty and
right.
These two ideas are basically defined by reference to each other
in the Enlightenment's language of liberation. Liberty is the
essence of right -- right being an interest in doing some things
free from interference by others and in protecting the produce
of that doing. Right essentially forms the just boundary of liberty.
But why ought men to be free to do some things? And free to do
what things, specifically?
The answers given by the Enlightenment to these questions announced
that at heart the Enlightenment was a battle for the authority
to re-define man (as the naturally solitary "self")
and to name the interests of the "self" that ought to
be the basis for the good political regime. Reason was to be the
new and sole authority supervising political (and intellectual)
life, supplanting the authority of revelation and ecclesiastical
structures.
The Enlightenment thinkers succeeded in winning the claim to that
authority. Each man was proclaimed by the enlighteners to be an
autonomous and naturally stable self, divided in the pre-enlightened
world, but split between nature and society not between body and
soul as the ancients had asserted. The enlighteners proclaimed
that man was solitary by nature, and though he lived everywhere
in association with other men he was unhappy in those associations
because they were not based on the interests of a naturally solitary
being. And the enlighteners proclaimed that because man is naturally
a whole and not an amalgamation or a composite of essentially
dissimilar elements -- body and soul -- there might be a way for
him to stay whole in society, if motivations to associate could
be found that appealed to what was real in his natural self and
not to virtues engendered by false notions of a "soul".
At least a part of each of those three proclamations is false,
as I shall demonstrate.
John Locke asserted that one of the things that was real in the
self was the self's desire for preservation, that this was evident
from everyone's fear of violent death. This overarching desire
comprised the desires for food, clothing, shelter, health, and
protection from predation (especially inter-human predation).
He posited that one way to heal the split in man was to base society
on a man's natural desires for these things and on a man's realization
-- arrived at from an education founded on reason -- that he could
acquire them better and hold on to them more easily by declaring
war on Mother Nature instead of on other men, a war of all against
all being the normal condition of naturally solitary man.
One of the cornerstones of this peace among men, according to
Locke, was to be the recognition that what a man labored to obtain
ought to be his. Another cornerstone was to be the recognition
that the attainment of his material necessaries was slowed down
when Reason was shackled by false authorities.
In practice this was to mean that because each man is unique each
man ought to be free to utilize his Reason as he sees fit, for
any interference in the use of a man's Reason is an impediment
to the progress promised by the philosophic disciplines -- science,
mathematics, and philosophy itself -- in subjugating Nature.
According to Locke, these freedoms to reason for oneself and to
seek and possess property were a man's natural right because
they allowed a man to be whole, which was necessary if he was
to achieve happiness.
But through this natural right doorway of liberty
created by Locke also passed a great deal of License. License
in the social realm, license in the political realm, and license
in the economic realm. This occurred in part because of the theories
of democratism (popular sovereignty) that developed logically
from the conception of man as a self who was naturally solitary.
It occurred also in part because of epistemological efforts to
shrink the scope of the legitimate claims to moral knowledge.
And it occurred in part because of Locke's error of introducing
an unnatural species of right in his analysis of property
rights.
The structure of economic and political power we now have is a
direct outgrowth of Locke's errors.
Jean Jacques Rousseau had his doubts that Locke's look into the
interests of the self had penetrated deeply enough. Rousseau saw
underlying those desires for preservation something more basic.
The fact that man wanted to avoid death meant that being alive
was good, desirable. But what was it in life that was desirable?
Rousseau answered in the main incorrectly because he, like Locke,
allowed himself to be split on the false dichotomy of nature-society.
The view of man as a naturally solitary "self" who is
split by various aspects of society, a view which has hypnotized
modern psychology in its other-directed/self-directed guise, hypnotized
Rousseau, too. Split on the false dichotomy, Rousseau saw as the
more basic experience of existence enjoyment in the life of the
mind and art, contemplating beauty, reposing the mind in the truths
it has discovered, the activities of noble idleness. These were
the things wanted most deeply, and these were the things Locke's
industrious economic creature -- the bourgeois -- had not
time to attain or enjoy.
By intentionally disregarding a momentous occurrence, and constructing
the artificial notion of man as naturally solitary and in a state
of war with all other natural men, both Locke and Rousseau created
a barrier that prevented the correct identification of the source
of man's unhappiness in society. Much of modern intellectual life
has been lived in that artificial tangle, consumed in playing
out the confrontation between the two men's false ideas about
a journey made by a fictitious creature.
3. A MOMENTOUS OCCURRENCE
We know little or nothing of the moment of
origin of several traditional social institutions, institutions
that exist to this very day, and that are still crucial (though
withering) constituents in social cohesion. The experiences that
led to their formation are experiences of which there is little
or no tangible record. And it is doubtful whether we have the
imagination to recreate fully and accurately those experiences
and to live imaginarily in them for even a few moments. Nonetheless,
the very lifecycle of a human tells us something of the greatest
import about the individual and his relation to society -- some
semblance of socialization, perhaps even some semblance of one
or more of the ancient social institutions that still exist, existed
at the moment man appeared on the planet, and when man entered
the world he entered as part of a social fabric, however loosely
or tightly woven it may have been.
The momentous fact of a priori socialization held a key
that was there for the using, and both Locke and Rousseau (and
a host of others) disregarded it and busily set about denaturing
man so he would fit into a fiction they had created.
At the risk of overemphasis I reiterate: Man is not, nor ever
could have been solitary by nature. We disregard that fact at
the peril of our civilization.
Within that fact about man's nature -- the fact of a priori
socialization -- lies a desire at least as basic as any asserted
by Locke or Rousseau. It is this desire unfulfilled that is the
source of the longing which Rousseau detected in the unhappy bourgeois.
The ancients were acutely aware of the existence of this desire,
and much of ancient society was structured to fulfill it. It is
capable of tempering anti-social impulses, and of motivating us
to do properly much of the work Locke'e theory exhorts us to doing
without proper restraint. It is the glue that makes social cohesion
possible. And it is at the same time a vital source of societal
vitality.
4. VALUED PLACE
This crucial desire is the desire for Valued
Place.
A working definition of Valued Place is needed here, and I offer
the following: Valued Place is a functional place within a group
that is succeeding in accomplishing its tasks. This functional
place gives the individual the opportunity to attain the pleasure
of satisfaction in accomplishing a task that is relevant to his
needs and to the needs of his community, and it gives him a sense
of being valued by others who would miss him if he was absent
from his place.
The desire for Valued Place interlocks all the varied and varying
desires that we must each prioritize as time and circumstances
demand. Without it it is impossible to comprehend fully the idea
of Right Desire to which Aristotle pointed us as a touchstone
of truth about Good and Bad in human behavior. And it is only
with Right Desire that we can strip from liberty the contaminant
of license and properly formulate right .
Next, then, a brief look at Right Desire.
5. RIGHT DESIRE
In his Nichomachean Ethics (Book 6, section
2) Aristotle suggested that there was another type of truth besides
the truth that conforms to things as they really are. This other
type of truth conforms to Right Desire.
Right Desire is a concept that was overlooked or disregarded by
Enlightenment thinkers, and that continues to be disregarded today
by many thinkers -- with disastrous results. Without it a problem
posed by David Hume's assertion is insoluble.
David Hume asserted that a prescriptive conclusion cannot be drawn
from a premise that is entirely descriptive. Hume's assertion
is one of the underpinnings of the moral relativism that pervades
modern thought. This relativism proclaims that if Hume's assertion
is correct, then there can be no valid "ought" judgements
-- and what a man does can be judged only on how well it achieves
for him the fulfillment of his desires. Moral relativism is a
concern in the context of properly conceiving liberty for
the obvious reason that it removes from the concept of liberty
any boundaries set by what is objectively good for man, and extends
the boundaries of liberty to some nebulous region of Utility in
maximizing pleasure and ease. Hume's assertion was crucial to
removing the moral claims of religion from the realm of knowledge
and consigning them to the realm of opinion -- a desirable outcome
in the eyes of the enlighteners.
But Relativism's proclamation is not correct, because of the existence
of a truth that conforms to Right Desire.
What is Right Desire?
As its name implies, it is the desire to seek what we ought to.
And what ought we to seek? Simply answering, " The good,"
won't solve the problem of subjectivism and relativism because
Baruch Spinoza is certainly correct that we often call a thing
good because we desire it -- even if the thing is not always
good in fact, and may be an apparent good merely.
The problem can be solved by differentiating between types of
desires. One type of desire we acquire as a result of our experiences,
these desires differ from individual to individual and from time
to time. Another type of desire is that which inheres in man's
nature, and these desires are therefore the same (in kind, if
not in degree) in all members of the human species. From here
on I'll use the phrase natural need to refer to particulars
of the type of desire that inheres in our nature, and acquired
want to refer to particulars of the other type of desire.
We cannot have a natural need to seek and to possess when attained
anything in a degree of excess that injures our ability to fulfill
all our natural needs, or to a degree of excess that knowingly
and unnecessarily injures other's ability to fulfill all their
natural needs. This is so because that which makes a man's unity
possible cannot at the same time and in the same respect make
that man's unity impossible. This unity -- the unified totality
of a whole life enriched by all one's rightly fulfilled needs,
needs that are mutually interdependent and complimentary and counter-balancing
when fulfilled -- is happiness, philosophically conceived
to be the total good. And because (as we shall soon see) some
of our natural needs are for certain types of association with
men whose efforts to attain happiness we are aiding, the prohibition
against injurious excess extends to that which is injurious to
others.
Thus all our desires for that which fulfills our natural needs
are Right Desires, and whatever fulfills a natural need is an
actual good, not merely an apparent good -- whether we have a
noticeable desire for it or not.
This difference between natural need and acquired want makes possible
the statement of the following self-evident truth: We ought to
seek whatever is good (whatever we have a natural need for) and
nothing else.
This self-evident truth makes possible the solution of the problem
posed by David Hume's assertion.
By starting with the above self-evident truth as a premise and
superadding a descriptive truth about human nature, one can move
to a conclusion that contains prescriptive truth. This means that
an "ought" judgement has objective truth if it is an
expression of a desire for a good in a degree that fulfills a
natural need. This in turn means that one may move certain moral
judgements from the realm of opinion -- subjective and relative
-- to the realm of knowledge -- objective and absolute.
This concept of Right Desire gives us some objective means with
which to determine the boundary between liberty and license (to
determine what is "excessive acquisition", for example),
means which will help to clarify what one has a right to. And
it corrects the Enlightenment error that man can be made whole
by throwing off certain virtues the origin of which was putatively
ascribed by the Enlightenment to be the false notion of the "soul".
6. NATURAL GOODS OF ASSOCIATION
The fact that some ways of associating not
only fail to fulfill natural needs but are injurious to one's
ability to obtain naturally needed association at all makes the
selection of the means of associating a subject of vital import.
And this fact raises a question: How can it be that a creature
who is naturally social is even capable of anti-social behavior?
The answer to this question is found in the fact that man does
not enter the world with a fully actualized set of instincts (endowments
of knowledge and preformed patterns of behavior in accordance
with that knowledge) adequate to all his needs. Instead, he is
endowed with a set of potentialities that are barely, if at all,
actualized at the moment he comes into the world. The barely actualized
potentialities are the sources of those instinctive impulses upon
which we act when young (and upon which we act when we are older,
but no wiser). Man has a potentiality for social behavior. He
also has a potentiality for aggressive violence which if not actualized
rightly makes for war when war is not needed, detrimental.
The intellectual methods (beyond trial and error) by which humans
develop their potentialites for social behavior are difficult
to ascertain with precision. Jean Piaget suggested that because
logic appears to be incompletely developed in young children it
is likely that one method involves at its earlier stages a process
that is not wholly rationally deductive. Piaget suggests this
method consists of matching the reactions of one person whom the
child is observing to the prior actions of another person whom
the child has observed -- matching these reactions to actions
more as reactions by the one to the "signals" from the
other than as rationally chosen responses to "situations".
Piaget's analysis concluded with the assertion that a form of
infant determinism is at work. Recent studies are finding evidence
that a childhood environment deficient in examples of adults interacting
cooperatively and collaboratively leaves the child deficient in
these social skills, but not completely irremedially so -- indicating
that Piaget's determinism is unfounded, and that what is actually
occuring in very young children is "habituation" merely.
This growing body of evidence supports the conclusion that it
is a natural need of humans to have the type of association that
imparts to us the social technique of cooperation and collaboration,
lest we learn primarily the techniques of acquiring whatever we
desire by a vicious form of competition (based on the use of brute
force) -- techniques that injure our ability to acquire natural
goods available to us only through association.
What are these goods that we are deprived of through a vicious
form of competition? What is this vicious form of competition?
And how does it work to deprive us of these goods?
Some of the important goods are: Sources of Valued Place; the
cohesive and stable nurturing environment from which children
learn much of their social technique; effectual social controls;
and, the genuine participation in communal affairs that makes
possible genuine, not merely numerical, individuation.
I have already defined Valued Place and taken a brief look at
the stable nurturing environment that facilitates acquiring the
habits of cooperation and collaboration.
Effectual social controls are all the various ways in which
a society brings to the attention of a member any behavior by
that member (short of outright criminality) which is injurious
to himself or the society. The more numerous and widepread throughout
a person's life that social controls are the more effective their
combined action in helping the individual to keep his behavior
within right limits and to return to behavior that is within right
limits when powerful wrong desires seduce him outside of those
limits. It is important to note that by social controls I mean
primarily the threat of the loss of things desired by the individual
which he obtains through the consent of others. Punishment inflicted
by impersonal entities, or restrictions forcibly imposed by impersonal
entities for the purpose of preventing the individual from withdrawing
his allegiance to the community are not social controls in the
sense that I am using the phrase.
Genuine participation in communal affairs means, foremost,
influential participation in the selection of means by which the
different groups of which one is a part go about accomplishing
their tasks.
What is the vicious form of competition that deprives us of these
goods?
7. THE BRUTE FORCE RIGHTS
Rights is one of those Enlightenment terms that has to
do with defining what we may fence other people off from, which
is what we think of as liberty. According to the lexicon of the
Enlightenment there are two varieties of rights. Natural
rights are those rights we have by virtue of the needs common
to us all which flow from our human nature. Social compact
rights are ostensibly those rights we acquire by virtue of
consentual compacts with other men. In his Essay Concerning
The True Original, Extent, And End Of Civil-Government John
Locke pointed out the distinction between these two varieties
of rights.
In the chapter Of Property Locke noted that men had a natural
common right to that which they could obtain by foraging,
and that the limits of this natural right were set by personal
need and waste -- a man had a right to only what he could, without
waste, personally consume (use) to satisfy his natural needs.
Locke also noted that men had a natural common right to appropriate
land from the common, and that the limits of this natural right
were set by waste and by leaving "enough, and as good left"
for those as yet unprovided for.
Locke went on to note that at some point in human affairs men
conferred on themselves, by virtue of compact, the right to greater
amounts of land and other property. This social compact right
quickly created a condition in which there was no longer land
"enough, and as good left" in the world freely accessible
to the unpropertied. This condition gave to land some value beyond
that which labor and ingenuity added to it -- the value of human-created
scarcity. This added value meant that a man had a right to claim
large possessions of property and to let it go to waste -- for
even waste land had some value to the owner now that there was
no longer land "enough, and as good left". Thus, the
right to waste became part of the bundle of property rights.
The existence of the fences, physical and legal, made possible
by the social compact right to large possessions of land,
now deprive many men of free access to material necessaries with
which to mix their labor. These fences, and the guns that defend
them, are what put teeth into an owner's demand that his terms
of trade be met or else, they enforce his or else
-- his withholding access to his property, his wasting that property
if he wishes. They superadd to the value of the property that
is contributed by labor and ingenuity the vicious value resulting
from human-created scarcity, a vicious value that Pierre Joseph
Proudhon boldly asserted made such conventions of property ownership
legalized theft. It is important to keep in mind that the superadded
value is vicious because there is now no longer "enough,
and as good left" in the world.
If there was still freely accessible land "enough, and as
good left" in the world, the value added to an owner's land
(and the property derived from it ) by the right to waste
would be only that value freely added as a result of the would-be
trader's willingness to trade more of his labor (or produce) --
physical, or intellectual, or both -- for the land (or goods)
that are to be potentially left to waste if the owner's terms
of trade are not met. The reasons for this willingness might include
an appreciation for the skill of the owner's workmanship, or an
appreciation of the ease which the ingeniously devised item will
make possible in the trader's future labors. This condition is
a truly Free-Market -- the values added to the items in the market
have no hint of coercion in them.
"Enough, and as good left" is a precise formulation
of the condition necessary to the existence of a Free-Market.
Because it is not possible for unpropertied men to travel great
distances when they are injuriously deprived of a material necessary,
the "enough, and as good left" condition must be understood
to apply locally -- that is, in practicable human terms -- and
not merely cosmically. It is logically unsound to claim that a
local market is free when the unnaturally scarce item in question
is freely available half-way across the world but the trip half-way
across the world is not physically practicable for those deprived
of the item locally. The use of the word available in that
context is absurd, making the sentence self-contradictory. For
example, if I appropriated from the common a parcel of land that
contained large quantities of a mineral necessary to human well-being
and there are no other deposits of the mineral locally, then the
market for that mineral would no longer be free -- the social
compact right to large possessions of that which I can't personally
consume would in this case introduce a value of coercion in the
trade, an or else that entailed injurious deprivation to
the would-be trader if he did not meet my terms of trade.
It ought to be clear now that in conditions of scarcity the right
to waste gives men a means of coercing out of other men more
in receipt for access to land (and the goods derived from it)
than is given. This coercively added value is one of the factors,
along with uncoercively added values placed on traded goods (labor
and property) by personal judgement and personal whim, that cause
the value of money to fluctuate in day to day use. And it is the
coercive power to cause the value of money to fluctuate -- power
derived from the right to waste -- that makes money useful
as a means of concentrating wealth. So it is that the right
to waste creates, in the form of money, a coercive means with
which to monopolize power over other men's lives -- the power
to control what they have access to and how they labor.
Why would any men consent, as Locke said they did, to a social
compact that tossed out all original limitations on the rightful
extent of property ownership? We now know why, in part -- because
it allowed those who consented to get more from their property
than they put into it. Even a man who was going to be put in a
servile condition by such a compact might consent to it so long
as that compact held out for him the possibility that he might
one day be able to use what he obtained through his servility
to gratify his desires for large possessions of property and the
mastery over men they make possible.
But, of course, not all men consented freely, tacitly or otherwise,
to the social compact that overthrew the rightful limitations
on property acquisition set by common natural need . Many already
lived in conditions of servility imposed on them by open violence
or by the threat of violence and injurious deprivation, and these
men accepted the "compact" in large part because they
had not the force of arms sufficient to defeat the force employed
to enforce it.
Locke's decision to avoid discussing the calculated violence (actually
committed and merely threatened) that was in reality a part of
the development of the social "compact" that made large
possessions of land a right is understandable. He was a
polemicist, interested in denaturing man in order to demonstrate
how the trip from nature to civil society is short and easy for
the "industrious" and "rational". It was not
prudent for him to shine too bright a light on the violence underlying
his social compact right. But the dissolving condition
of our society gives us some reason to question whether Locke
made an error by asserting that narrowly utilitarian social compacts
made by brute force and unconnected to natural need are
a proper basis for a political regime.
But consented to, or not, the social compact that granted the
status of right to owning large possessions of land and
controlling how others use that land and on what terms is the
soul of the vicious form of competition that is working to dissolve
society.
Rather than accept man's full nature and battle the social
compact that conferred the right to waste, Locke chose
to denature man and leave this corrosive force alone. We must
not follow his example.
How does this vicious form of competition work to deprive us of
the goods of association?
8.THE CORROSIVE PROCESSES OF COMPETITION
The process through which the failure to provide
these natural goods develops in a civilization is the same process
through which all known civilizations have been built.
In the early stages of civilization-building lines of communication
are developed that allow information, commodities, and labor to
move between the various territories that are coming under the
control of the centralizing authorities who are providing the
cohesive energy for the nascent civilization. If and when the
value of the information, commodities, and labor that moves along
these lines of communication becomes enhanced by the type of ownership
"convention" that confers the right to waste
on owners, then the coercion-created competition for wealth, and
the concentrations of wealth thus generated, create along these
lines of communication a flow of control of resources away from
the local communities and towards the centralizing (wealth controlling)
entities. The outflow of such forms of control to the centralizing
entities immediately creates spiraling effects -- the outflow
increasing whenever the diluting of a local (social, political,
or economic) group's relevance to its members weakens their allegiance
to the local group (or whenever the increased power gained by
the centralizing entity enables it to merely wrest away from the
local group another of the group's socially relevant functions).
An example of the consequences of this corrosive spiral effect
is the decrease in the effectiveness of social controls. When
a remote centralizing entity has acquired control of, say, a local
business and begins to offer advancement within the business without
any consideration of the individual's conduct within his local
community, the web of effectual social controls is weakened. The
more aspects of the individual's life that become detached from
consideration of his local community life, the less effectual
become the social controls. Eventually it is likely that the individual's
behavior begins to succumb to the seductions of whatever temptations
are strongest at the moment.
Spiral effects are not confined to merely personal conduct. The
outflow of control and power to the centralizing entities eventually
reaches the point at which the individual loses the sense of influence
(and most actual influence) in the direction of the affairs of
these colossi, and consequently in the direction of his own activities.
If an individual is forced by laws issued from a personally uninfluencable
remote authority to conduct the business of his life in ways unpalatable
to him, he will likely lose interest in participating in that
politics. Likewise, if an individual cannot obtain permission
to try to accomplish a task that is part of his livelihood in
a way he thinks will be an improvement on the existing method,
then the individual is likely to feel insecure and eventually
hostile toward the leadership of the enterprise at which he is
working. This hostility provides impetus to join groups that are
hostile to the centralizing entity's authority. Over time these
hostile groups work to hasten the dissolution of the civilization.
An important aspect of this loss of personal influence is a loss
of Valued Places. This loss is significant in itself, because
the individual's search for new Valued Places contributes to the
formation of those associations hostile to the civilization.
The loss of Valued Places is also significant because it is allied
with the developing failures of the mechanisms of societal vitality
caused by the right to waste.
9. ESSENTIAL INEQUALITY AND SOCIETAL VITALITY
What is it that constitutes a society's vitality?
A primary source of a society's vitality is beneficial strength
flowing freely to points of weakness. Societies disintegrate,
collapse, die, when this flow of beneficial strength to points
of weakness is impeded excessively.
Impediments to the free flow of beneficial strength to points
of weakness can be properly understood as Cost in human terms.
Some of the forms in which this cost is imposed are: Forcing one
into labors one does not value; forcing one into labors that consume
too much of one's day; limiting one's access to forms of labor
one values; and limiting one's ability to find associations in
which one may authentically participate personally in the political,
economic, and educational affairs of the community. All of these
forms of cost are imposed through covertly coercive means by civilizations
which have reached a definite level of social complexity that
the right to waste allows them to reach, and all reduce
one's ability to find Valued Place and genuine individuality.
An example of these covert impositions of cost is the need for
having money . This imposition has the effect of drawing
an inordinate amount of a society's intellectual vigor into economic
pursuits -- commercialism flourishes, and ingenuity is
directed towards devising means of increasing profits. One means
of increasing profits is increasing a man's productivity. As productivity
increases the cost of material necessaries decreases. The material
standard of acquisition (the "standard of living") increases
overall within society. Eventually, however, high-productivity
becomes hyper-productivity, and the necessity of having money
in the economic scheme that is now unbalanced by hyper-productivity
becomes hyper-corrosive, socially.
When hyper-productivity is achieved all the necessaries (goods
and services) of a society are produced or provided by a relatively
small fraction of the available labor of a society. In an economic
scheme powered by the manmade scarcity created and legitimized
by our right to waste, and in which goods and services
are distributed by money, this hyper-productivity means that there
are no longer enough jobs, the produce of which is in high demand
(and the wages of which are correspondingly high), to go around
-- and especially to go around to those who wish to support more
than themselves on their income. This is the point at which hyper-productivity
becomes socially hyper-corrosive.
Because most people need money with which to purchase goods and
services, and because most acquire money from working at a job,
hyper-productivity means that in addition to the necessaries-producing
jobs some sort of other jobs need to be created for folks to work
at and make money at -- and these jobs are in the aggregate lower-paying
than the now relatively scarce necessaries-producing jobs. (These
created jobs are relatively lower paying because their produce
is in low demand, or because they can be filled from a very large
labor pool.) These jobs are in an important sense artificially
created, and their advent and continued existence requires
that a desire for their produce likewise be created or heightened
artificially -- usually through the techniques of marketing.
The term Consumption Society has been coined to describe
this state of affairs. Through this process hyper-productivity
begins to make it more and more difficult for more and more persons
to support a family on a single income. As a result, a person
must either work more hours per week in order to support a family,
or more than one person in the family must go to work to make
money. The traditional family becomes less and less attractive
to more an more persons. The Valued Places it offers become scarcer
and scarcer.
The consequences of this loss of Valued Place are demoralization,
alienation, and all the social ills that attend those conditions
-- today these include crime, suicide, and addiction (to alcohol,
drugs, gambling, TV, electronic diversions, buying things, etc.).
Other losses of societal vitality resulting from the costs that
civilizations with long lines of communication between leaders
and the led impose on a society are throttled explorations (personal
and collective), falling rates of invention, falling rates of
political participation. and a skewing of the production of goods
and services towards undynamic and unnecessarily wasteful enterprises.
All of these losses of vitality are evident in America.
What is the genesis of this flow of beneficial strength to points
of weakness?
There is, manifestly, an essential inequality between humans --
some are male, some female, some are bigger, some more intelligent,
some more aggressive, etc. This essential inequality has as its
source a natural biological phenomenon that is largely beyond
the control of human agencies. It is this essential inequality
that creates the initial differential in strengths (physical and
intellectual) which makes possible the flow of relative strength
to relative weakness.
This essential inequality between persons is a vital factor in
the process of individuation that each human undertakes in the
quest for happiness -- making possible an individual that is distinct
from others in more than a purely numerical sense.
This essential inequality is also a vital factor in one's ability
to find Valued Places -- for a person in need of another's strength-in-aid
is a potential source of Valued Place for a person with the needed
strength.
This essential inequality between humans is not eradicable. But
it can be affected -- increased or decreased to some degree --
by human interventions. The process of beneficial intervention
in this regard, of strength aiding weakness to become non-weakness
when non-weakness is desirable, is itself part of the flow and
crucial to a society's vitality. We see this flow of beneficial
strength to weakness in the process of rearing children, in education,
in health care, etc.
Another source of societal vitality is competition between functionally
relevant associations for the allegiance of members.
Functionally relevant associations are embodiments of certain
values, of sets of goals, and of means with which to attain the
goals towards which those values direct us. The complex interplay
and competition between these associations is a rich source of
ingenuity, vital to the health of a society.
Further, this competition between functionally relevant associations
stimulates the desire to acquire genuine personal freedom of action
-- the freedom to choose between competing means of obtaining
natural goods. This is so because the desire for personal freedom
thrives on one's belief in the possibility that there can actually
exist competing external means between which one can choose to
obtain natural goods.
Any administrative scheme to monopolize the power of a society
must, in order to achieve and maintain its power monopoly, absorb
the socially relevant functions of institutions that are competing
with the scheme for functional relevance in society. This monopolization
of socially relevant functions effectively kills off the socially
vital competition between institutional means of obtaining natural
goods, just as it impedes the flow of beneficial strength to weakness
at the personal level -- killing off Valued Places. (In our era
the Impersonal Provider State and Capitalism in its State and
Corporate forms are exemplars of this type of administrative scheme
-- each fueled by the power of the right to waste.)
Both of these forces -- the right to waste that makes money
valuable, and the monopolistic administrative schemes of societal
power the right fuels -- operate through vicious competitive
mechanisms to disengage the individual from forms of association
that are vital to his obtaining all his natural goods. And not
only do they disengage the individual from associations that can
restrain him from giving into the Wrong Desires that result from
the buffetting we receive from the flux, they actively encourage
him to act licentiously and injuriously with regard to his own
happiness and the happiness of others. These are some of those
disastrous consequences that I suggested have come from the Enlightenment's
disregard for Aristotle's concept of Right Desire, from the Enlightenment's
erroneous conception of man as by nature solitary, and from the
license-contaminated notion of liberty and right that flow from
those oversights and errors.
10. EMERGING FROM THE ENLIGHTENMENT DARKNESS
With these insights in hand we are now able
to correct the radical errors in the Enlightenment notions of
liberty and right.
Properly understood, liberty -- when conceived as freedom
of action -- is bounded by Right Desire. A man ought to be free
to seek and to possess when obtained whatever he naturally needs.
And because every man is unique, he ought to be free to use whatever
means to fulfill a natural need that do not cause injury to his
ability to fulfill other natural needs, and that do not unnecessarily
injure another's ability to fulfill any natural needs.
From this conception of liberty and with our "ought"
judgments now firmly reconnected to natural needs we can see that
there is only one species of political right that is morally
defensible, that there is only one species of right that
we ought to have -- the species John Locke referred to as natural
common right. There are no morally valid rights that
derive from compact merely. This means that one has a right
-- a natural common right -- to seek and to possess when obtained
only that for which one has natural needs. When seeking and possessing
something not itself naturally needed results in the natural good
of satisfaction AND when the object sought is innocuous when possessed
-- that is, when its possession does not produce injurious privation
to anyone -- the pursuit and possession of such an object is also
a natural common right.
The attainment of our naturally needed goods is affected by time
and place -- by the local conditions in which individuals actually
live from moment to moment. At present many persons live in places
that are inadequate to all their needs -- and distribution of
resources from other locations to these locations is a necessity
for these persons. The right to waste, which is the foundation
of the means of production control and of distribution control
currently employed, is socially destructive. We need different,
non-destructive means. What means can we use?
Now that we have properly conceived the notions of liberty
and right and cleared away the rest of dark tangle of Enlightenment
errors we can begin to see means that are not socially corrosive
-- means that do not rest on the right to waste, but rather
rest on the desire for Valued Place.
With regard to land, the conventions of ownership that
allowed charging others for access to land are obviously manifestations
of license, and as such are morally wrong. Without these conventions
the grant of power to keep others from one's excess land or from
the produce of one's excess land becomes morally wrong, too. This
means that one has the natural common right to the exclusive
possession of only that land one's exclusive and personal consumption
of satisfies one's natural needs while not unnecessarily injuriously
depriving others -- exclusive possession of land to any greater
degree constitutes license and not liberty, and is therefore not
a right. (An exception to this is the case of ownership of excess
land when the excess is worked by the owner and the produce of
this excess land is not withheld from others on condition of the
owner receiving something in exchange for the produce. So long
as the owner of this land is not unnecessarily depriving anyone
of material necessaries by virtue of the way he is working the
excess, his possession of the land is innocuous, and his working
of it is a natural common right.) This, in course, means
that a great deal of the absentee ownership -- especially of rented
properties -- now countenanced by the right to waste would
cease to be a right. The distributism suggested by Hilaire
Belloc and G. K. Chesterton is worthy of a more thorough look
in light of these proper conceptions of liberty and right.
With property properly limited it is problematical that money
will have a use in society. This is so because if one cannot withhold
access by others to one's excess property, nor charge others for
access to one's excess property, money becomes nothing more than
a token of performed labor -- a token the value of which would
be reduced by inflation to worthlessness unless the type of labor
for which one could obtain a token was restricted. Such a restriction
would likely unvalue intellectual labor to some extent, as well
as unvalue other types of not purely materially productive labor
that are vital to a society. Another objection to such a restriction
is that due to the circumstances of time and place many persons
are not physically near an enterprise at which remunerated labor
could be performed, and they would therefore have no means of
earning money. But perhaps these objections will be overcome and
some form of money will be retained.
The unvaluing of money will have a profound effect on our political
power structures as well, as it must have on all power structures
that grew out of the Enlightenment's vision that a rational man
is primarily an Economic creature. The general tenor of the effects
throughout society will be to shorten lines of communication between
leaders and the led, to increase the value of personal authority
(an endogenous force) as it decreases the means of obtaining power
(an exogenous force), and to diffuse the power within society
into a variety of institutions as the ability of any administrative
scheme to monopolize power will be weakened by the loss of the
easy means of power concentration that was license-created wealth.
11. CONCLUSION
The changes in our way of living that will
flow from these proper conceptions of liberty and right
will present great challenges, challenges for which the vast
majority of persons in America are hungry. But the challenges
cannot be met, as we have seen, by persons whose minds are in
the thrall of the false idea that a human is by nature a solitary
and autonomous "self" -- that the individual has within
him, irrespective of his associational contexts, a stability of
personality, an enduring set of motivations to seek liberty and
order, and a nature comprising instincts and reason that can make
him autonomous, self-sufficing. The notion of an autonomous "self"
is as essentially false as the Nature-Society dichotomy of which
it was begotten.
A wiser vision of man is needed. Perhaps that wiser vision is
the vision presented in this essay: That man has a socialized
nature; that man can only find happiness through the right fulfilling
of all his natural needs, needs which are mutually complimentary,
mutually interdependent, and mutually counterbalancing -- each
fulfilled natural need a good that makes it possible to seek the
fulfillment of other needs; that possessing a social nature and
needs that are mutually complimentary, interdependent and counterbalancing,
our natural needs for the goods of association are intergral to
our happiness; that mutually complimentary, interdependent, and
counterbalancing, every good sought is a good in part because
it helps us to aid others to fulfill their natural needs; and,
that this nexus with society created by every man's mutually complimentary,
interdependent, and counter-balancing needs is the primary source
of societal vitality and cohesiveness, benefitting the strong
and the weak alike -- strengthening the weak, and stabilizing
the strong through his attainment of Valued Place.
Without this wiser vision, and instead saddled with the corrosive
trade-off between obtaining some goods at the expense of others
that is created by the false rights formulation bequeathed
to us by the Enlightenment, it will likely be our fate to endure
the dreary repetition of the decline and fall of another increasingly
inhumane civilization, ours