There is something very wrong with our concept of rights -- especially with the concept of social contract rights.
You can see what was amiss all along in the idea of social contract rights when you look at those plastic busts of Elvis grinning up at you from their neat little rows on the shelves of the mega-mart. In the long train of events that led to the creation of those plastic Elvises you can see the indiscriminate license, and waste, and eventually coerced waste that is the consequence of social contract rights in this finite world . It's an ugly thing, all that coerced Working For The Purpose Of Buying, all that coerced waste of the stuff of societal vitality -- imagination, ingenuity, genuine individuality. It's ugly and we don't look at it much. Instead, we gaze acquisitively at all the stuff lining the shelves of the mega-mart. But we had better take a hard look at it right now. It is the breeding ground for a species of worm that is eating away at our vitals. And the worm's meal has but a course or two left.
THE UNNATURAL RIGHT TO WASTE
Rights is one
of those concepts bequeathed to us by the Enlightenment. Rights
has to do with defining what we may fence other people off from,
which is how we have been schooled to think about liberty since
the Enlightenment. According to the lexicon of the Enlightenment
there are two varieties of rights. Natural rights
are those rights we have by virtue of the needs that are common
to us all, needs that are common to us all because they inhere
in our common human nature. Social contract rights are
those rights we ostensibly acquire by virtue of consentual compacts
with other men. In his Essay Concerning The True Original,
Extent, And End Of Civil-Government a prominent Enlightener,
John Locke, gave us examples of these two varieties of rights.
In the chapter Of Property Locke noted that men had a natural
common right to that which they could obtain by foraging,
and that the limits of this natural right were set by personal
need and waste -- a man had an exclusive right to only what he
could, without waste, personally consume (use) to satisfy his
natural needs. Locke also noted that men had a natural common
right to appropriate land from the common, and that the limits
of this natural right were set by need and waste and by leaving
"enough, and as good left" for those as yet unprovided
for.
Locke went on to note that at some point in human affairs men
conferred on themselves, by virtue of compact, the right to greater
amounts of land and other property. This social contract right
quickly created a condition in which there was no longer land
"enough, and as good left" in the world freely accessible
to the unpropertied. This condition gave to land some value beyond
that which labor and ingenuity added to it -- the value of human-created
scarcity. This added value meant that a man had a right not only
to claim large possessions of property but to let it go to waste
-- for even waste land had some value to the owner now
that there was no longer land "enough, and as good left".
Thus the social contract right to own and to waste large
possessions of land became part of the bundle of established property
rights.
FENCES AND UNFREE MARKETS
The existence of the fences, physical and legal,
made possible by the social contract right to large possessions
of land, now deprive many men of free access to material necessaries
with which to mix their labor. These fences, and the guns that
defend them, are what put teeth into an owner's demand that his
terms of trade be met or else, they enforce his or else
-- his withholding access to his property, his wasting that property
if he wishes. As I pointed out, they superadd to the value of
the property that is contributed by labor and ingenuity the value
resulting from human-created scarcity, a vicious value. It is
important to keep in mind that the superadded value is vicious
because there is now no longer "enough, and as good left"
in the world freely accessible to all.
If there was still freely accessible land "enough, and as
good left" in the world, the value added to an owner's land
(and the property derived from it ) by the social contract
right to large possessions of land would be only that value
freely added as a result of the would-be trader's willingness
to trade more of his labor (or produce) -- physical, or intellectual,
or both -- for the land (or other property) that is to be potentially
left to waste if the owner's terms of trade are not met. The reasons
for this willingness might include an appreciation of the skill
of the owner's workmanship, or an appreciation of the ease which
the ingeniously devised item will make possible in the trader's
future labors, or an appreciation of the location of the property.
This condition is a truly Free-Market -- the values added to the
items in the market have no hint of coercion in them.
"Enough, and as good left" is a precise formulation
of the condition necessary to the existence of a Free-Market.
Because it is not possible for unpropertied men to travel great
distances when they are injuriously deprived of a material necessary,
the "enough, and as good left" condition must be understood
to apply locally -- that is, in practicable human terms -- and
not merely cosmically. It is logically unsound to claim that a
local market is free when the unnaturally scarce item in question
is freely available half-way across the world but the trip half-way
across the world is not physically practicable for those deprived
of the item locally. The use of the word available in that
context is absurd, making the sentence self-contradictory. For
example, if I appropriated from the common a parcel of land that
contained large quantities of a mineral necessary to human well-being
and there are no other deposits of the mineral locally, then the
market for that mineral would no longer be free -- the social
contract right to large possessions of that which I can't
personally consume would in this case introduce a value of coercion
in the local trade for that mineral, an or else that entailed
injurious deprivation to the would-be trader if he did not meet
my terms of trade.
Why would any men consent, as Locke said they did, to a social
compact that tossed out all original limitations on the rightful
extent of property ownership? We now know why, in part -- because
it allowed those who consented to get more from their property
than they put into it. Even a man who was going to be put in a
servile condition by such a compact might consent to it so long
as that compact held out for him the possibility that he might
one day be able to use what he obtained through his servility
to gratify his desires for large possessions of property and the
mastery over men they make possible.
But, of course, not all men consented freely, tacitly or otherwise,
to the social compact that overthrew the rightful limitations
on property acquisition set by common natural need . Many already
lived in conditions of servility imposed on them by open violence
or by the threat of violence and injurious deprivation, and these
men accepted the "compact" in large part because they
had not the force of arms sufficient to defeat the force employed
to enforce it.
Locke's decision to avoid discussing the calculated violence (actually
committed and merely threatened) that was in reality a part of
the development of the social "compact" that made large
possessions of land a right is understandable. He was a
polemicist, interested in denaturing man in order to demonstrate
how the trip from nature to civil society is short and easy for
the "industrious" and "rational". It was not
prudent for him to shine too bright a light on the violence underlying
his social contract right. But the dissolving condition
of our society gives us some reason to question whether Locke
made an error by asserting that narrowly utilitarian social compacts
made by brute force and unconnected to natural need are
a proper basis for a political regime.
For the sake of clear understanding and analysis the social
contract rights that are asserted by Enlightenment polemicists
to be the product of freely given consent ought to be renamed.
The new name ought to reflect the element of coercion that actually
underlies these so-called rights. I shall use the term violence-created
rights .
THE WORM
I have demonstrated how in conditions of scarcity
the violence-created right to own large possessions of
land and to control how others use that land and on what terms
gives men a means of coercing out of other men more in receipt
for access to land (and the goods derived from it) than is given.
This coercion is the merely first in an appalling train of consequences.
The vicious value created by this coercion (along with uncoercive
values placed on traded goods by personal judgment and personal
whim) causes the value of money to fluctuate in day to day use.
Here is a simple example of how the coercion causes this fluctuation.
(I give this example mindful that it is sometimes risky in a complex
world to simplify, and with all due apologies to Karl Marx and
Eugen Bohm-Bawerk, who examined these mechanisms very thoroughly.)
One man owns a bread making enterprise -- including the land from
which the ingredients and machinery and fuel and packaging used
in bread making are produced. This land cost him practically nothing
to purchase. Another man, who has no property but himself, works
at the bread making enterprise and buys the bread from the enterprise.
The laborer performs over the course of a year all the different
types of labor that are required to produce the ingredients and
machinery and fuel that he uses to make the bread. For this he
is paid a wage that does not vary as his tasks vary. In the end
it turns out that he receives one dollar for each loaf of bread
he produces.
The owner sells a loaf of bread to the laborer for two dollars.
The laborer pays this price because he has not the means to make
bread himself for less -- all the land in the world is already
owned and he has not enough money to buy land and start a bread
making enterprise.
So, when the owner spends a dollar he gets a loaf of bread for
it, but when the laborer spends a dollar he gets only half a loaf
of bread for it. The property owner's power of setting the terms
of these trades is what causes the value of that dollar to fluctuate.
The coercive power of the property owner to make the value of
money fluctuate in his favor helps the property owner to accumulate
money -- which creates a further advantage for him in property
acquisition. The value to the owner of some of his large sum of
money may differ from the value to the laborer of the laborer's
small sum of money. The owner's second million dollars may not
be as precious to him dollar for dollar as any of the laborer's
hundred dollars is to the laborer. (Bohm-Bawerk explained this
phenomenon in part with the concept of marginal utility
.) This means that the owner may be willing to part with more
of his many dollars for a piece of property he wants to buy than
the laborer is willing (or able) to part with. Thus, marginal
utility works to aid the wealthier in acquiring more and more
property -- furthering the imbalance of the power to cause the
value of money to fluctuate in the wealthier's favor.
The mechanisms of trade veil this coercion-induced fluctuation
in the value of money, but it is almost always there -- often
moreso because it is veiled. It is this veiled coercive power
to cause the value of money to fluctuate -- power derived from
the violence-created right to own large possessions of
land and control how others use it -- that makes this violence-created
right especially efficient as a means of concentrating wealth
and accumulating money. And because money is the primary means
with which land and property are exchanged in our system, so it
is that this violence-created right creates a means with
which to accumulate power over other men's lives -- the power
to control what they have access to and how they labor.
This means of accumulating power facilitates the creation of monopolistic
administrative schemes of power. The simplified example I just
gave demonstrates the means by which corporations, for instance,
are able to accumulate money and property at such an accelerated
rate. Monopolistic schemes of power are the species of worm that
is eating away at our social cohesion.
Some of these monopolistic schemes have the effect of draining
from vital social institutions their socially relevant functions,
which in turn deprives the members of these institutions of Valued
Places and personal influence in communal affairs -- the things
needed in order for genuine individuality to flourish. Others
coerce us into forms of labor that we do not value, that do not
obtain for us the human goods that labor must obtain for us if
we are to find satisfaction in it.
For a century these monopolistic schemes have been worrisome to
men concerned with the preservation of personal liberty. But the
efforts at defanging the monopolizing power of the schemes --
largely formulated around the idea of administrative decentralization
and diversification of power -- have come to naught, or
worse. They have come to naught because they have not come to
grips with the means of power monopolization that empower these
schemes. They have come to worse than naught because they have
reinforced the notion that these schemes can be defanged by better
administrative techniques, merely. So long as the means of power
monopolization are readily available, they will be used, and no
efforts at balancing power within a society will long succeed.
An examination of these schemes at work will demonstrate this
point.
POWER LUST -- THE GATEKEEPER MENTALITY
A society that encourages and facilitates the
acquisition and fencing-off of large possessions of land, for
the purpose of setting the terms of the use of that land, cultivates
a Gatekeeper Mentality in some of its people. This Gatekeeper
Mentality is different in kind from the self-defense mentality
of the person who is interested only in protecting what he owns
and uses personally to satisfy his natural needs. The latter bent
of mind is motivated by the desire for personal freedom. The Gatekeeper
Mentality is also different in kind from simple greed and miserliness,
which seeks merely to possess for the sake of possessing. The
Gatekeeper Mentality is characterized by its desire for the power
to control and direct the use of the resources of others. It is
not merely interested in keeping others out, but in selecting
who shall be let in, and on what terms.
The Gatekeeper Mentality carries with it the drive to create a
certain amount of uniformity in others. This drive flows from
the managerial hubris of the Gatekeeper -- the Gatekeeper is so
certain his way is a better way that he is willing to force others
to do things his way. It is this managerial hubris that sets the
Gatekeeper to the task of monopolizing the control of the way
things are done.
Though it appears that a symbiotic modus vivendi (The Third
Way?) is being reached between the Gatekeeper Elites, there still
exists some distinction between the predominantly commercial and
the predominantly political schemes of power controlled by them.
These schemes are still sufficiently distinct that they operate
along converging lines of social destructiveness for a while.
So, for a while I will treat them separately.
OVERBEARING MONEY
The commercial scheme works in the main by
imposing on most of us the necessity of having money .
This imposition has the effect of drawing an inordinate amount
of a society's intellectual vigor into economic pursuits -- commercialism
flourishes, and much of a society's ingenuity is directed
towards devising means of increasing profits. One means of increasing
profits is increasing a man's productivity. As productivity increases
the cost of material necessaries decreases. The material standard
of acquisition (the "standard of living") increases
overall within society. Eventually, however, high-productivity
becomes hyper-productivity, and the necessity of having money
in the economic scheme that is now unbalanced by hyper-productivity
becomes hyper-corrosive, socially.
When hyper-productivity is achieved all the necessaries (goods
and services) of a society are produced or provided by a relatively
small fraction of the available labor of a society. In an economic
scheme powered by the manmade scarcity created and legitimized
by our violence-created right to large possessions of property,
and in which goods and services are distributed by money, this
hyper-productivity means that there are no longer enough jobs,
the produce of which is in high demand (and the wages of which
are correspondingly high), to go around -- and especially to go
around to those who wish to support more than themselves on their
income. This is the point at which hyper-productivity becomes
socially hyper-corrosive.
Because most people need money with which to purchase goods and
services, and because most acquire money from working at a job,
hyper-productivity means that in addition to the necessaries-producing
jobs some sort of other jobs need to be created for folks to work
at and make money at -- and these jobs are in the aggregate lower-paying
than the now relatively scarce necessaries-producing jobs. (These
created jobs are relatively lower paying because their produce
is in low demand, or because they can be filled from a very large
labor pool.) These jobs are in an important sense artificially
created, and their advent and continued existence requires
that a desire for their produce likewise be created or heightened
artificially -- usually through the techniques of marketing.
The term Consumption Society has been coined to describe
this state of affairs. Through this process hyper-productivity
begins to make it more and more difficult for more and more persons
to support a family on a single income. As a result, a person
must either work more hours per week in order to support a family,
or more than one person in the family must go to work to make
money.
The corrosive effect on the traditionally-structured family of
this commercial Gatekeeper power scheme -- the Consumption Society
-- is obvious, but it is not the only Gatekeeper scheme that acts
to dissolve the family.
DOMINEERING CREDENTIALISM
The managerial hubris cultivated in the Gatekeeper
Elite who dwell within the economic sphere is replicated in the
Gatekeeper Elite who dwell in the political sphere. It is exemplified
by the idea of improving men through their education, an
idea given full voice by enlighteners from Plato to Locke to Rousseau
to Horace Mann. Obligatory government-controlled schooling is
its most prominent apparition. It appeared on the scene to weaken
the family by draining away the family's traditional educative
function at the moment hyper-productivity commenced its assault.
The political Gatekeeper Elite has set about monopolizing not
only the education of children, but of all members of society.
This Gatekeeper Elite has relentlessly worked to drain from labor-unions
and professional guilds their educative and labor-directing functions
by imposing government licensing schemes.
The scope of the license schemes is not confined to the labor
formerly under the auspices of guilds and unions, but is expanding
on a daily basis throughout the professional and occupational
universe -- forcing people to acquire a government-approved education
and to navigate through all manner of Gatekeeper-imposed complications,
thereby fencing off a segment of society from certain valued forms
of labor, and thereby exacerbating the wealth skewing effects
of the hyper-productivity that has been induced and legitimized
by the violence-created right to large possessions
of property. These fences are literally blocking the flow of the
lifeblood of societal vitality -- the flow of beneficial personal
strength to weakness, from which we acquire our Valued Places.
THE PROVIDER STATE
With the dissolution of the family proceeding
apace in consequence of the corrosive commercial and educational
power monopolies, the managerial hubris of the political Gatekeeper
Elite has moved them to take on the remaining tasks of the family,
neighborhood, and church. And in addition they have been working
hard to bring into existence new managerial tasks never before
undertaken by any administrative schemers -- the administration
of nationwide health care distribution schemes, for example.
The socially corrosive effects of the latest manifestations of
the Provider State are of the same tenor as the effects of the
government's education monopolization scheme. These schemes have
drained vital functions from the social institutions that used
to stand between the individual and the state. As these vital
functions have drained away so to has the the allegiance of people
to those institutions. And as those institutions have withered
the opportunities they gave to people for finding Valued Places
and personal influence in communal affairs have withered, too.
The alienation and isolation that have followed in the wake of
this vitality drain, and the social pathologies that alienation
and isolation feed -- violent crime, addiction, illegitimacy --
have created even more opportunities for managerial hubris to
flourish.
A thorough look at every corrosive manifestation of the Provider
State is beyond the scope of this essay. But one aspect of the
Provider State has been given too little attention, and its neglect
is part and parcel of the blank failure to stem the worm's insinuation
into every nook and cranny of life. That aspect is the Empowering
Class.
THE EMPOWERING CLASS
I have demonstrated how a system of property
ownership rights that was established by open violence,
the threat of open violence, and by "compact", and which
the passage of time has conventionalized, has empowered the commercial
Gatekeeper Elite. But the political Gatekeeper Elite have not
been empowered by that established system of violence-created
rights of property alone. They have been empowered
also by the Empowering Class of democratic citizens, who are empowered
by other violence-created rights.
The democratic citizen, a creature who is treated by our politics
(and by the fallacious 17th century view of human nature on which
our politics is based) as an atom, is not a natural being. He
is quite literally a figment of the human imagination, come to
life.
He is imagined to be a naturally solitary "self" who
has within him the capacity to be autonomous, self-sufficing.
This imagined nature is as essentially false as the Nature-Society
dichotomy of which it was begotten -- the experiences of the isolate
and the fact of mankind's a priori socialization demonstrate
this conclusively.
This citizen atom is schooled by our culture to calculate his
narrowly "enlightened" self-interest within an essentially
economic formula. He is also schooled by our culture to exercise
his violence-created rights -- that is, to build fences
around as much as he can. And he is schooled to use the political
system in order to protect those violence-created rights.
This schooling results in a creature who thinks a great deal about
money, and about what other persons have control of that he would
like to have control of, and about making political "compacts"
in order to get that control. He is something of a petty tyrant.
In a modern society -- hyper-productive, license-based, waste-driven
-- this creature is a powerful political entity. But his political
power is not easy for him to personally wield effectually. In
fact, the theory of democratism that gave him this political power
makes it possible for him to wield it effectually only when he
is wielding it as part of a majority. This fact makes the power
practicably meaningless to the citizen atom from time to time
-- whenever he is in the minority. All of which makes political
organizers important to the citizen atom -- as it makes him important
to them.
The citizen atom has something else that is important to the political
organizer -- money; money with which to hire Gatekeepers and policemen
and weapons with which to guard fences and control gates, for
control of fences and gates is the way power over men is wielded
in a society based on violence-created rights. Pierre Joseph
Proudhon put it well, "Money, money, always money -- this
is the crux of democracy."
The desires for money and control of resources cultivated in the
citizen atom by our culture, the vicious conditions of competition
in our culture of violence-created rights that make the
citizen atom feel enslaved to varying degrees, the importance
of the citizen atom to the political organizers who in our democratized
culture offer him a chance to play master, these make the citizen
atom a relatively willing and powerful accomplice in putting over
the schemes of power monopoly hatched by the political Gatekeeper
mentality. Through and through this citizen atom is a creature
of violence-created rights.
And so it is that the total politicization of life is so easily
being accomplished by the political Gatekeeper Elite. Even the
creation of a nationwide health care system is not beyond the
power hungry Gatekeeper with such accomplices at hand,
EMERGING FROM ENLIGHTENMENT DARKNESS
The social dissolution being wrought by the
worm that has been bred on violence-created rights will
not be stopped by tinkering with the administrative structures
of power in our culture, not so long as these rights continue
to be enforced. Nor will preaching the virtues of responsibility
to corporations and citizens slow the worm's corrosive progress.
To rid ourselves of the worm we shall have to deprive him of his
breeding ground -- the social contract rights (violence-created
rights) that are an indiscriminate license to fence folks
off from what they need free access to. This will require
a precise formulation of right, a more precise formulation
than has been bequeathed to us by the Enlightenment. With that
precise formulation in hand we can begin the task of unlearning
the schooling we have received about the righteousness of our
mis-named social contract rights.
One difficulty that we are immediately faced with in precisely
formulating right is the question of whether our judgments
about what is and what is not a righteous human desire have any
objectively valid basis. If we cannot demonstrate that they do,
then we shall be unable to establish any objective criteria for
judging what we ought to have a right to. We will then
be left with the old formulations of the boundary of right --
"I have a right to do anything that doesn't injure someone
else" or "I have a right to do anything that doesn't
injure the Common Good" -- formulations that leave only subjective
calculations of utility, and brute force, as the judge and enforcer
of what is "needless" and "injurious to others"
and the "Common Good".
The Enlighteners and their followers made tremendous epistomological
efforts to remove moral judgments from the realm of knowledge
and to consign those judgments to the realm of mere opinion. In
doing so they chose to disconnect right from need,
and connected it to utility and promiscuous desire -- opening
the door to the indiscriminate license that is plaguing us now.
We shall have to work hard now to undo their efforts. Aristotle
gave us the tool with which to do this work -- the concept of
Right Desire.
RIGHT DESIRE
In his Nichomachean Ethics (Book 6, section
2) Aristotle suggested that there was another type of truth besides
the truth that conforms to things as they really are. This other
type of truth conforms to Right Desire.
Without the concept of Right Desire a problem posed by an insight
David Hume made is insoluble.
David Hume saw that a prescriptive conclusion cannot be drawn
from a premise that is entirely descriptive. Hume's insight is
one of the underpinnings of the moral relativism that has pervaded
moral philosophy since the Enlightenment. This relativism proclaims
that if Hume's assertion is correct, then there can be no valid
"ought" judgments -- and what a man does can be judged
only on how well it achieves for him the fulfillment of his desires.
Moral relativism is a problem in the context of properly conceiving
liberty and right for the obvious reason that it
removes from the concept of liberty and right any boundaries set
by what is objectively good for man, and extends the boundaries
of liberty to some nebulous region of Utility in maximizing pleasure
and ease. Hume's assertion was crucial to removing the moral claims
of religion from the realm of knowledge and to consigning them
to the realm of opinion.
But Relativism's proclamation is not correct, because of the existence
of a truth that conforms to Right Desire.
What is Right Desire?
As its name implies, it is the desire to seek what we ought to.
And what ought we to seek? Simply answering, " The good,"
won't solve the problem of subjectivism and relativism because
Baruch Spinoza is certainly correct that we often call a thing
good merely because we desire it.
The problem can be solved by differentiating between types of
desires. One type of desire we acquire as a result of our experiences,
these desires differ from individual to individual and from time
to time. Another type of desire is that which inheres in man's
nature, and these desires are therefore the same (in kind, if
not in degree) in all members of the human species. From here
on I'll use the phrase natural need to refer to particulars
of the type of desire that inheres in our nature, and acquired
want to refer to particulars of the other type of desire.
We cannot have a natural need to seek and to possess when
attained anything in a degree of excess that injures our ability
to fulfill all our natural needs, or to a degree that knowingly
and unnecessarily injures other's ability to fulfill all their
natural needs. This is so because that which makes a man's unity
possible cannot at the same time and in the same respect make
that man's unity impossible. This unity -- the unified totality
of a whole life enriched by all one's rightly fulfilled needs,
needs which are mutually interdependent and complimentary and
counter-balancing when fulfilled -- is happiness, philosophically
conceived to be the total good. And because some of our natural
needs are for certain types of association with men whose
efforts to attain happiness we are aiding, the prohibition against
injurious excess extends to that which is injurious to others.
Thus all our desires for that which fulfills our natural needs
are Right Desires, and whatever fulfills a natural need
is an actual good, not merely an apparent good -- whether we have
a noticeable desire for it or not.
This difference between natural need and acquired want makes possible
the statement of the following self-evident truth: We ought to
seek whatever is good (whatever we have a natural need for) and
nothing else.
This self-evident truth makes possible the solution of the problem
posed by David Hume's insight.
By starting with the above self-evident truth as a premise and
superadding a descriptive truth about human nature, one can move
to a conclusion that contains prescriptive truth. This means that
an "ought" judgment has objective truth if it is an
expression of a desire for a good in a degree that fulfills a
natural need. This in turn means that one may move certain
moral judgments from the realm of opinion -- subjective and relative
-- to the realm of knowledge -- objective and absolute.
This concept of Right Desire gives us some objective means with
which to determine the boundary between liberty and license, means
which will help to clarify what one has a right to.
THE PROPER FORMULATION OF RIGHT
With our "ought" judgments now firmly
reconnected to natural needs we can see that there is only
one species of political right that is morally defensible,
that there is only one species of right that we ought to
have -- the species John Locke referred to as natural common
right. There are no morally valid rights that derive
from compact merely. This means that one has a right -- a natural
common right -- to seek and to possess when obtained only
that for which one has natural needs. When seeking and
possessing something not itself naturally needed results in the
natural good of satisfaction AND when the object sought is innocuous
when possessed -- that is, when its possession does not produce
injurious privation to anyone -- the pursuit and possession of
such an object is also a natural common right.
With regard to land, this means that one has the natural common
right to the exclusive possession of only that land one's
exclusive and personal consumption of satisfies one's natural
needs -- exclusive possession of land to any greater degree constitutes
license and not liberty, and is not a right. (An exception to
this is the case of ownership of excess land when the excess is
worked by the owner and the produce of this excess land is not
withheld from others on condition of the owner receiving something
in exchange for the produce. So long as the owner of this land
is not unnecessarily depriving anyone of material necessaries
by virtue of the way he is working the excess, his possession
of the land is innocuous, and his working of it is a natural
common right.)
This means, in course, that a great deal of the absentee ownership
-- especially of rented properties -- now countenanced by the
violence-created rights to large possessions of property
is not properly a right. The distributism suggested by
Hilaire Belloc and G. K. Chesterton is worthy of a more thorough
look in light of this proper conception of natural common right.
This proper formulation of natural common right will have
a profound effect on our political power structures as well, as
it must have on all power structures that grew out of the Enlightenment's
vision that a rational man is primarily an Economic creature.
The general tenor of the effects throughout society will be to
shorten lines of communication between leaders and the led, to
increase the value of personal authority (an endogenous force)
as it decreases the means of obtaining power (an exogenous force),
and to diffuse the power within society into a variety of institutions
as the ability of any administrative scheme to monopolize power
will be weakened by the loss of the easy means of power concentration
that was license-created wealth.
CONCLUSION
To unlearn the fallacious schooling we have
received about our rights we will, however, need more than
the proper formulation of natural common right. We will
also need to liberate our thinking from the notion of "self"
that shackles us today -- the notion that a human is by nature
a solitary and autonomous "self", that the individual
has within him, irrespective of his associational contexts, a
stability of personality, an enduring set of motivations to seek
liberty and order, and a nature comprising instincts and reason
that can make him autonomous, self-sufficing. At the risk of overemphasis
I reiterate -- the fact of man's a priori socialization
and the experiences of the isolate demonstrate conclusively that
this notion of an autonomous "self" is as essentially
false as the Nature-Society dichotomy of which it was begotten.
A wiser vision of man is needed -- perhaps this vision: That man
has a socialized nature; that man can only find happiness through
the right fulfilling of all his natural needs, needs which are
mutually complimentary, mutually interdependent, and mutually
counterbalancing -- each fulfilled natural need a good that makes
it possible to seek the fulfillment of other needs; that possessing
a social nature and needs that are mutually complimentary, interdependent
and counterbalancing, our natural needs for the goods of association
are integral to our happiness; that mutually complimentary, interdependent,
and counterbalancing, every good sought is a good in part because
it helps us to aid others to fulfill their natural needs; and,
that this nexus with society created by every man's mutually complimentary,
interdependent, and counter-balancing needs is the primary source
of societal vitality and cohesiveness, benefiting the strong and
the weak alike -- strengthening the weak, and stabilizing the
strong through his attainment of Valued Place.
Without this wiser vision, and instead saddled with the corrosive
rights formulation bequeathed to us by the Enlightenment,
it will likely be our fate to endure the dreary repetition of
the decline and fall of another increasingly inhumane civilization,
ours.
Whitefish, Montana -- November 2000